"We aren't saying anything there, one way or another, about the probability that the world is like that. We're not saying anything about the probability that Nethys would, if we could ask him or Ione could, write CORRECT on our sheet of paper, if we wrote down the guess, 'all-10s have a 10% propensity to YES'. To say that we'd need to know the 'prior-probability' of that hypothesis, and the 'prior' on all the other hypotheses, and have already computed the likelihood of all the other hypotheses, and 'renormalized' to get the 'posterior'."
"Which isn't a sort of thing that experimental reports try to do. Other people could know other evidence that would be relevant to whether Nethys was likely to write CORRECT on the guess. Stating probabilities like that are what prediction markets are for."
"What we're saying is - just flatly suppose that the world is in utter fact a place where all-10s have a 10% propensity to solve the 2-4-6 challenge within 30 minutes, relative to the experimental procedure we're using. Then it is valid, as a matter of 'logical-deduction', to say that you're 9% likely to get a NO followed by a YES on the first two subjects tested. It is likewise valid to say that, flatly assuming the hypothetical world where all-10s have a 20% YES propensity, you have a 16% chance of getting a NO followed by a YES."
"This is the key fact that other people need to know in order to update their beliefs based on your experimental results, so it's what the experimental report summarizes."
"It's a very local fact. It's like how, if you suppose that X=3 and Y=4, you can calculate that X*Y=12 without worrying about whether Z=5 or Z=7."
"If somebody else already ran tests on 100 subjects with all-10s, they might have seen results that pretty strongly updated them on the chance that Nethys would write 'CORRECT' on the 20%-propensity-hypothesis. They could've gotten 80 YES results, for example, which would make them pretty sure that hypothesis was wrong."
"But they can't have gotten any results relevant to the proposition that, in the hypothetical world where 20% of all-10s guess within 30 minutes given our experimental procedure, there's a 16% chance that we'll get a NO followed by a YES."
"You don't need to read all of the experimental reports in the world, you don't need to follow any prediction markets, to report that summary of the results you got."
"Suppose your third, fourth, and fifth results are YES, NO, NO."
"After the third result, we've seen data that's 0.9*0.1*0.1 = 0.009 likely in the 10%-propensity world, and that we'd have a 0.8*0.2*0.2 = 0.032 chance of getting in the 20%-propensity world."
"After the fourth result, a NO, we've seen things we're 0.0081 likely to get in the 10% world, and 0.0256 likely to get given 20% propensity."
"After the fifth result, a NO, it's 0.00729 or 729/100000, and... haha, whoops, 0.02048 or 2048/100000 for 20% propensity."
"This, by the way, being among the reasons not to trust your teacher even when he seems like such an uncomplicated straightforward reliable person, it is literally actually possible for him to be mistaken."